R.G. Collingwood
on the Ancient Greek worldview
These notes are based on two books by historian and
philosopher R.G. Collingwood. For convenience of expression, I have often
omitted saying “according to Collingwood.”
From Collingwood’s The Idea of Nature
1. The Ancient Greek idea of nature Collingwood says that the Ancient Greeks thought of the natural
world as follows:
·
The natural world is a world of
bodies in motion.
·
There is motion because the natural
world as a whole is a living organism.
·
There is not just motion but also
orderly motion.
·
This orderly motion is because the
natural world as a whole is a rational organism, is
doing things for reason.
·
Every creature within it
participates in the life of this whole organism and also realizes the reasons
of this organism.
·
The orderly motion within nature is
what makes a science of nature possible.
When explaining these thoughts, Collingwood does not specify
whether the natural world covers the whole of reality, or whether there are
aspects of reality which for the Ancient Greeks are not aspects of the natural
world. But he does say that for Ancient Greeks generally, the mind is part of
the natural world. There may be some who think differently but these exceptions
go against the prevailing current of Ancient Greek thought. (In The Idea of History, Collingwood implies
that the Ancient Greeks did not take mathematical objects, such as numbers and
geometric figures, as part of nature.)
2. Contrast with the Renaissance idea Collingwood says that in the period of history known as the
Renaissance, an alternative idea of nature emerged. Here is a summary of this
alternative:
·
The natural world as a whole is not
a living organism.
·
The natural world exhibits orderly
motion, but this is not because the natural world as a whole is moving
according to its own reasons.
·
The orderly motion is the product
of intelligence, but in the way that the motions of an unintelligent machine
are the product of intelligence: they are the products of an intelligent
designer.
·
A quote capturing the Renaissance
idea: the natural world is “an arrangement of bodily parts designed and put
together and set going by an intelligent mind outside itself, for a definite
purpose.” (p. 5)
·
This intelligent mind is God.
One of the major problems for this worldview is how to relate
minds to this conception of nature. If nature is an unintelligent machine, it
seems we must say that intelligent minds are outside it, but then they seem to
affect bodies through decisions: how can this be possible?
3. The role of analogy Both of
the ideas of nature above are the product of analogies. The Ancient Greek
person formed a conception of himself (or herself) and
thought of the whole of nature as a living being exhibiting similar
characteristics. Collingwood writes:
…he comes to think of himself as a body whose parts are in
constant rhythmic motion, these motions being delicately adjusted to each other
so as to preserve the vitality of the whole and at the same time he finds
himself to be a mind directing the activity of this body in accordance with his
own desires. The world of nature as a whole is then explained as macrocosm to
this microcosm. (p. 8)
The Renaissance view of nature is based on the experience of
designing and constructing machines. The Ancient Greeks were not machine users
except to a very small extent and their catapults and water-clocks were not
prominent enough in their lives to affect how they thought about nature as a
whole. In the Renaissance, machines were a much bigger part of everyday life,
making an analogy with machines more likely. Collingwood lists the printing
press, the windmill, the pump, the pulley, the lever and the wheelbarrow as
examples.
4. The Ancient Greek view of change The Ancient Greeks believed that nature was in a continuous state
of change, but they regarded these changes as part of a cycle. A change from state (a) to state (b) is part of a larger process in
which state (a) will eventually return. If an Ancient Greek came across
a change that on the face of it does not appear to be part of a cycle, such as
the change from youth to older age, they would either regard it as part of a
larger cycle which was not fully known or easily apparent; or else as a
mutilated fragment of a cycle – if the process had proceeded normally, there
would be a return to an earlier state.
The Renaissance view of change does not appear to have this
commitment.
From Collingwood’s The Idea of History
1. The Ancient Greek conception of knowledge The Ancient Greeks thought that in order to properly know
something it had to be something unchanging. Nothing external to it and nothing
internal to it would cause it to change. They thought of the objects of
mathematical knowledge as meeting these conditions.
This conception of knowledge led to puzzles about whether history
and nature could be known, since human history and the natural world are full
of change. The Greeks distinguished between knowledge proper and something
which is translated by opinion. The Greeks do not seem to think of this
‘opinion’ as something illusory but as a kind of semi-knowledge.
(More elaboration is needed here. Furthermore, there is a question
of consistency with what Collingwood says in The Idea of Nature, because in that book the natural world is
presented as an object of science for the Ancient Greeks. Collingwood is aware
of the puzzle, but I do not think he says enough to resolve it or regarding how
the Greeks dealt with it.)
2. Ancient Greek consciousness of historical change Although the Ancient Greeks pursued the
ideal of unchanging eternal objects of knowledge, they were also aware of human
history. They had what Collingwood calls historical consciousness. But when
they thought about change in human affairs, they did not think about the gradual
development of a tradition, rather sudden changes from one human extreme to
another:
·
The Ancient Greeks thought that “an
excess in any one direction led to a violent change into its own opposite” (p.
23): from smallness to greatness, from pride to abasement, from happiness to
misery, from wealth to poverty, etc.
·
They observed such changes, but
they did not claim to know why the changes occurred.
·
Herodotus said that the Gods
rejoice in upsetting and disturbing things.
·
This view of sudden change from one
excess to another was expressed in Greek tragedies.
(There is also a question of consistency here, because how does
this picture of change fit with the cyclical view of nature attributed to the
Ancient Greeks in The Idea of Nature?
The Ancient Greek conception of nature included human beings and their minds as
part of nature, so is this catastrophic change part of a larger cycle in which
the original state returns? These are questions Collingwood does not address.)
References
Collingwood, R.G. 1945. The idea of nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Collingwood, R.G. 1946. The idea of history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.