F.
H. Bradley on ‘Why should I be moral?’
The problem of the amoralist
The problem of the amoralist
is the problem of answering the question ‘Why should I be moral?’ so as to
give an amoralist a reason to be moral. The
problem would be solved if one could do this. But some philosophers think that
the question itself is a bad one and so that the problem ought to be rejected,
not solved. F.H. Bradley sounds as if he is taking up this position in his 1876
essay Why should I be moral? But, in fact, he
rejects what he treats as the normal way of understanding the question,
yet does offer a reformulated version of it.
An argument for answering the question
Before making a case for rejecting the
question, Bradley considers an argument for why the question is a good one.
Anyone who thinks that the question ought to be rejected needs to be able to
identify a problem with this argument.
Here is how Bradley states the
argument:
“To
ask the question Why? is
rational; for reason teaches us to do nothing blindly, nothing without end or
aim. She teaches us that what is good must be good for something, and that what
is good for nothing is not good at all. And so we take
it as certain that there is an end on one side, means on the other; and that
only if the end is good, and the means conduce to it, have we a right to say
the means are good. It is rational, then, always to inquire, Why
should I do it?”
This argument can be reconstructed as
follows:
(1) For any
instruction to do something it is rational to inquire into the end or aim of
doing that thing.
(2) The instruction
‘Be moral’ asks us to do something.
(3) To ask ‘Why
should I be moral?’ is to inquire into the end or aim of doing what
the instruction ‘Be moral’ asks us to do.
Therefore:
(4) It is rational
to ask ‘Why be moral?’
An argument against answering the
question
Here is an argument Bradley presents
against answering the question:
“But
here the question seems strange. For morality (and she too is reason) teaches
us that, if we look on her only as good for something else, we never in that
case have seen her at all. She says that she is an end to be desired for her
own sake, and not as a means to something beyond. Degrade her, and she
disappears; and to keep her we must love her and not merely use her. And so at
the question Why? we are in trouble, for that does
assume and does take for granted that virtue in this sense is unreal, and what
we believe is false.”
The argument here against answering
the question can be reconstructed as follows:
(1) Whatever is against morality is
against reason.
(2) To answer a question one must accept
all assumptions of the question.
(3) An assumption of the question ‘Why
should I be moral?’ is that morality is not an end in itself, rather at best a
means to an end.
(4) Accepting this assumption is against
morality.
Therefore:
(5) To answer the question ‘Why should I
be moral?’ is against reason.
The
arguments that Bradley presents give rise to a dilemma over whether or not to
answer the question. The argument against motivates him to inquire into the
background commitments of the assumption he identifies.
Bradley’s
analysis of the assumption
Bradley observes that the assumption
identified – that morality is at best a means to an end – must depend on one of two background
doctrines:
(i) Nothing
is valuable as an end in itself. Whatever is good is good only as a means.
(ii) There is something which is
valuable as an end in itself, but it is not morality.
Bradley thinks that if we point out a
range of things that morality is good as a means for achieving, then whoever asks the question will not be satisfied, and
this reveals that their background doctrine cannot be (i):
“If
we said to them, for example: “Virtue is a means, and so is
everything besides, and a means to everything else besides. Virtue is a means
to pleasure, pain, health, disease, wealth, poverty, and is a good because a
means; and so also with pain, poverty, etc. They are all good because all are
means. Is this what you mean by the question Why?”
They would answer No. And they would answer No because
something has been taken as an end, and therefore good, and has been assumed
dogmatically.”
Bradley observes that since the person
asking the question must be committed to doctrine (ii), they too must reject
the question of ‘What for?’ except they must reject it for whatever end they
have in mind, while the person committed to morality must reject it for virtue.
Therefore while they might appear to be pursuing the requirements of
rationality in asking, ‘Why should I be moral?’ whereas people who try to be
moral without having an answer to this question appear to be dogmatic, actually
they are not less dogmatic.
A reformulation of the question
Bradley comes to the following
conclusion about the question he has analysed:
“Has
the question, Why should I be moral? no sense then, and is no positive answer possible? No, the
question has no sense at all; it is simply unmeaning unless it is equivalent
to, Is morality an end in itself; and, if so, how and
in what way is it an end?”
I think Bradley’s belief is that if one wants to formulate a question which must be addressed because it is required by rationality, then the ‘Why should I be moral?’ question must be formulated as he does in the quotation.
Bradley thinks that the voice of moral
consciousness tells us to regard morality as an end in itself and
that this in itself gives us reason for doing so.
Reference
Bradley, F.H. 1876. ‘Why should I be moral?’ in Ethical
Studies. London: Henry. S. King & Co.