H.A.
Prichard on promising
The Paradox
Prichard
presents a paradox regarding promises:
(i) If you promise another that you will do an action, then
you bring into existence an obligation on you to do that action.
(ii) It is
impossible to bring into existence an obligation.
Prichard does
not explain why we should hold (ii), beyond comparing the fact that there is a
certain obligation to a mathematical fact. But there are certain properties
which one might plausibly attribute to an obligation to do X that make it
puzzling how one could bring into existence such a thing:
Objectivity – an
obligation to do X objectively exists;
Normativity – an
obligation to do X is something that ought to be fulfilled;
Non-mentality – an
obligation to do X is not a mental entity;
Non-physicality – an
obligation to do X is not a physical entity.
Regarding
objectivity, if the obligation is felt to exist, objective existence means that
it does not merely feel as if it exists. It really does exist.
Regarding non-mentality, the obligation is not a mind or a feature of a mind.
One might think that there could still be an obligation even if it is not felt
or believed in, in which case there seems no reason to think of it as a feature
of a mind. (Objectivity and non-mentality may sound much the same, but they are
not.)
The General Shape of a Solution
Prichard
thinks that on reflection, we will accept something like (ii). We will accept
the following commitment:
(ii*) It is impossible to directly bring into existence an
obligation.
The notion of
directly, as opposed to indirectly, bringing about the existence of something
needs clarification. Prichard does not define it, but he does give some helpful
examples of indirectly bringing about an obligation. Here are two.
Example 1. You
have wrongly hurt someone’s feelings. By directly bringing about this state of
affairs, you indirectly bring into existence an obligation: to try to make them
feel better.
Example 2. You
become a parent. By directly bringing about this state of affairs, you
indirectly bring into existence an obligation on you to care for your child.
(In both
cases, it seems that the obligation arises not just because of your action but
also because of some prior conditional, e.g. if you are a parent, you must care
for your child.)
According to
Prichard, we must think of promising to do X as directly bringing about
the existence of something and by bringing into existence this thing,
indirectly bringing into existence the obligation to do X. Presumably, whatever
the direct thing is, it should be highly counterintuitive to deny that we can
bring into existence this thing, unlike with obligations.
The Expectation Account
The basic idea
behind the expectation account is that when you promise me to do X, you
directly bring into existence an expectation in me that you will do X. This
gives rise to an obligation on you to do X.
Prichard gives some examples to challenge this basic idea. He also completely rejects expectation accounts, whatever qualifications one might add to the basic idea. Prichard’s argument is not formulated with enough clarity, I think. What follows is an argument that his text suggested to me, though it is hard to tell how close it is to what he had in mind.
An
advocate of the expectation account cannot reasonably say that an expectation
brought into existence by promising gives rise to an obligation unless the
expectation is justified. There are no obligations from unjustified
expectations, e.g. irrational ones. We can therefore represent what the
expectation account requires as follows:
Promise made by you to do Xà Justified expectation in the
addressee that you will do X à Obligation on you to do X as
a consequence
Prichard thinks that the
person addressed by the promise can only justify expecting you to do what you
promised by appealing to the premise that you are under an obligation. But how
can they support this premise? How can they support thinking that you are under
an obligation? If they must appeal to the premise that they have a justified
expectation to explain why you are under an obligation, as the expectation
account insists, then they will be assuming the existence of what they are
trying to establish: a justified expectation.
The General Promise Account
According
to this account, when one makes a specific promise, what one does is bring into
existence certain sounds in connection to a specified action, e.g. the sounds
you make when you say ‘I promise’ followed by specifying a course of action.
The reason why making these sounds results in an obligation to do the
action specified is because of a general promise which you earlier made:
to never make these sounds to another person, followed by specifying a course
of action, unless you go on to pursue that course of action.
A
puzzle that Prichard raises about the general promise is how it can
happen within language, given that the person who
makes the promise has not previously agreed to only utter certain sounds
in connection with a course of action if they go on to pursue that course of
action.
Nevertheless,
Prichard thinks that there must be something like a general promise, even if it
is not a promise and even if it is not something in language, which
explains why our specific promises obligate. In other words, the process of
initiation into promising language involves something like making a promise to
keep one’s promises. He acknowledges that this end to his paper is not a
final solution, rather a point from which to engage in further inquiry.
Reference
Prichard,
H.A. 2002. The Obligation to Keep a Promise. In H.A. Prichard and J. MacAdam, Moral
Writings. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Link.