Joseph Raz on
autonomy
Below are
some theses and arguments that Jonathan Quong
attributes to Joseph Raz in chapter two of his book Liberalism Without
Perfection. Note that the formulations of these theses and the
reconstructions of the arguments are Quong’s, not
mine. I have just extracted them from the chapter and put them here.
Two Theses
According to
Quong, Raz is committed to
the following theses:
Argument
from Autonomy Thesis: Principles of liberal toleration are best, or
most plausibly, justified by appealing to the intrinsic or inherent value of
leading an autonomous life.
The Liberal Perfectionist Thesis (LPT): It is at
least sometimes legitimate for a liberal state to promote or discourage
particular activities, ideals, or ways of life on grounds relating to their
inherent or intrinsic value, or on the basis of other metaphysical claims.
Raz on autonomy
According to
Quong, Raz holds that the
following are necessary conditions for autonomy:
a. Adequate mental abilities.
b. Adequate range of options.
c. Independence from coercion and
manipulation.
Quong also says that the following are three other noteworthy features
of Raz’s conception of autonomy:
d. Autonomous people have integrity.
e. Autonomy presupposes weak value
pluralism.
f. Autonomy is only valuable when directed
towards good or worthwhile ways of life.
Pluralism theses
Weak value pluralism is the thesis that ‘there
are various forms and styles of life which exemplify different virtues and
which are incompatible’.
(Quong, quoting Raz)
Another value pluralism thesis is competitive
value pluralism: this adds to weak value pluralism the
further claim that some of these valuable ways of life are not only
incompatible with other valuable forms of life, but also intolerant of those other forms. Raz appeals
to this thesis in one of his arguments.
Raz’s argument from pluralism for toleration
1. Autonomy requires an adequate range of
options, that is, a reasonable diversity of social forms available to choose
from.
2. Competitive value pluralism means people
who pursue different valuable forms of life will tend to be intolerant of other
valuable forms of life.
3. Competitive value pluralism will, if
unchecked, lead to intolerance and suppression, thereby reducing the number of
valuable forms of life available, possibly to the extent that there is an
inadequate range from which individuals can choose.
4. Competitive value pluralism is true.
5. Therefore a political principle of
toleration is necessary to preserve one of the necessary conditions of
autonomy.
Raz’s argument for the harm principle
The basic idea of the harm principle, according
to Quong, is that the only reason which can
serve to legitimate the use of coercion against someone is to prevent that
person from causing harm.
Quong attributes the following lengthy argument to Raz in favour of a qualified version of this principle. I
think the argument is best split into halves:
6. Autonomous life is possible and valuable
only when there is an adequate range of good options from which to choose.
7. We are all under prima facie moral
duties to provide others with the minimal conditions necessary to lead a
valuable autonomous life.
8. Therefore we are each under a prima
facie duty to help provide others with good options.
9. Failing to provide others with what we
owe to them is a form of harm.
10. The harm principle permits us to use
coercion to prevent harm.
11. Therefore the harm principle permits us
to use coercion to raise the taxes which are used to fund an adequate range of
good options.
12. Preventing people from pursuing bad
options is in principle consistent with the value of autonomy, since autonomy
is only valuable insofar as it is spent in pursuit of good options.
13. But the state can only feasibly prevent
people from pursuing bad options by threatening coercive sanctions (e.g. fines
or imprisonment).
14. Coercive sanctions reduce people's
negative liberty to choose good options.
15. Therefore coercive sanctions reduce
people's ability to autonomously choose the good.
16. We should not reduce people's ability
to autonomously choose the good in order to prevent them from choosing badly.
If we combine the halves we get this:
17. Therefore we should endorse the following
version of the harm principle: it is wrong to coerce people in order to prevent
them from pursuing bad options (via 13-16), but (via 6–11) it is not wrong to
use coercion to force people to fulfil the moral duty they have to help provide
others with good options.
Reference
Quong, J. 2010. Liberalism
Without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
(You can
find a paper on Quong’s objection to a perfectionist
argument against political liberalism here.)