Joseph Raz on
promises
In his paper ‘Promises and
Obligations’, Raz contrasts two conceptions of a
promise, supporting the second over the first.
The Intention Conception
According
to the intention conception, to promise to perform an action is to communicate
a firm intention to perform that action.
The
intention conception is associated with following principle:
(PI) In normal circumstances, if you communicate a firm
intention to perform an action to someone else and you are aware that they
might rely on you, you ought to perform the action and the person you address
has a right that you do so (unless they release you from the requirement to
perform the action).
‘Normal
circumstances’ is my term, used here so that certain cases are excluded. Raz’s examples of such cases are promises to do something
intrinsically immoral and promises made under duress.
Criticism 1
What
I am calling the first criticism is an intricate argument, which is not easy to
assess. Raz presents a challenging example to the
intention conception, then introduces a response in defence of the intention
conception, then introduces an alternative response that rejects this
conception altogether and then argues in favour of this alternative response.
The intention conception: to promise to perform an action is to communicate a firm intention to
perform that action.
Raz’s
challenging example. One person tells another that he firmly
intends to do X, but also that he does not promise to do X.
A defence of the intention conception: this person is conceptually confused.
Raz’s
alternative response to the example: ‘the
intention conception fails to distinguish adequately between promises and other
phenomena.’ (1977: 217)
Raz argues for his alternative response
like so: (1) the (PI) principle associated with the intention conception is
based on certain considerations; (2) these considerations entail that promises
and various other things provide identical reasons for action; (3) but promises
and these other things do not provide identical reasons for action; (4) given
that this is so, the alternative response is more persuasive than the defence.
Regarding
(1), Raz identifies two considerations in favour of
the (PI) principle:
(i) others
who count on us acting in accordance with our expressed intentions may be
disadvantaged or harmed if we do not then act on them;
(ii) we
benefit from a reputation of reliability by acting in accordance with our
expressed intentions.
In
support of (2) and (3), Raz gives examples of where
these considerations fail to register differences between promises and other
things. I shall present one of these examples. One person, A, promises another, B,
that he will perform a certain action. A third person, C, is present and A is
aware that C may rely on A performing this action in making his
own plans. Not only may C rely on A, he may also think A unreliable if A does not perform the action.
So, in support of (2), the considerations in favour of the (PI) principle
entail that A has a reason to perform the action that is the same as if A
had promised C that he would perform the action. In support of (3), it
does not seem that the fact that C
may rely on A and the fact that he
may think A unreliable if A does not perform the action produce a
reason for A that is identical to a reason from a promise.
Criticism 2
The
second criticism that Raz makes is that the intention
conception cannot do justice to three features of promises: they impose
obligations; these obligations are voluntary; and the reasons that result from
them are based on rules. I will focus on the first of these features: a reason
for doing X that results from a promise to do X is
based on rules (or a rule).
Raz’s argument regarding rules and the
intention conception is as follows:
(1) The intention conception can only do justice to the fact that the reason
from a promise is based on rules if the (PI) principle is a rule.
(2) If, whenever this principle applies, it applies because the considerations
in favour of the principle affect the balance of reasons, so that on balance
one should abide by the principle, then the (PI) principle is not a rule.
(3) Whenever the principle applies, it applies because the considerations in
favour of the (PI) principle affect the balance of reasons, so that on balance
one should abide by the principle.
From
(2) and (3):
(4) The (PI) principle is not a rule.
From
(1) and (4):
(5) The intention conception cannot do justice to the fact that the reason
from a promise is based on rules.
To
understand this argument better, consider a person who has made a promise to do
something but now has a reason not to do it, for instance because it is
inconvenient for them. The two considerations in favour of the (PI) principle
mentioned in the previous section weigh against this reason of inconvenience:
the other person will be counting on them; they may lose the benefits of a
reputation for reliability. If these considerations are weighty enough, they
will outweigh the reason of inconvenience, so that the balance of reasons
points towards them keeping the promise. But rules, according to Raz, do not work like this. Rules are based on certain
considerations but they are independent reasons for action, rather than simply those
considerations shifting the balance of reasons in a certain direction.
Rules
as Exclusionary Reasons
As
Raz conceives of rules, a valid rule that one ought
to do action X has two aspects to it:
(i) it
is a reason to do X
(ii) if
there are reasons for not doing X, the rule is a reason for not acting on these
reasons.
The
rule must be based on considerations for doing X. It is a reason to do X
because of these background considerations for doing X. Another
word for ‘considerations’ here is ‘reasons’. Raz
says that the rule, as a reason to do X, ‘relays the force of the reasons for
doing X’ on which it is based (1977: 221).
But
how then is it a reason of its own and not just these considerations in favour of
doing X, these background reasons? If a rule only had the first aspect, it
would not have independent force as a reason. The second aspect, according to Raz, explains how it has independent force. A rule is not
meant to function by the background considerations in favour of it affecting
the balance of reasons, so that on balance one should do X. The second aspect
of a rule means that, if valid, it functions as a reason against acting on any
reasons for not doing X – an exclusionary reason, in Raz’s
terminology. (Note: I am wondering if (ii) should be reworded as: if there are reasons for not doing X, the
rule is a reason for not
taking into account those reasons. Raz’s account
makes much more sense then. See below.)
The
simplest way of making sense of an exclusionary reason is as follows. If there
is a valid rule that one ought to do X, one should not decide whether to do X
by evaluating whether the background considerations upon which the rule is
based outweigh any reasons for not doing X. One should think, ‘I have a reason
to bypass this weighing-up process and ignore any reasons for not doing X in
evaluating whether to do X.’ Note: it seems as if Raz
is onto something, in saying that rules are not meant to function by affecting
the balance of reasons, but there is debate over how to interpret his idea
of an exclusionary reason and also over whether we can make sense of his
thinking in a defensible way.
The
Obligation Conception
According to the obligation conception, a promise is an expression of an
intention to undertake an obligation.
The
obligation conception is associated with the following principle:
(PO) In normal circumstances, if you communicate an
intention to, by this very act of communication, take on an obligation to
perform a certain action and to give whoever you are addressing a right that
the action be performed, then you ought to perform the action and the
addressee has a right that you do so.
The
(PO) principle is a rule. When you promise, the combination of your
particular promise and this general rule together produce a reason for you to
perform the action specified in the promise. Each is a partial reason; together
they are a complete reason (1977: 219).
Justifying
the (PO) Principle
A
valid rule has considerations justifying it, or at least one consideration.
What are the considerations justifying the (PO) principle?
The
way in which promises work, by exclusionary reasons, creates a special kind of
relationship between the person who promised (the promisor) and the person
addressed (the promisee). The promisor must honour
the promise to the promisee, and cannot escape it
merely by appealing to strong reasons that weigh against keeping the promise –
that would be to regard the reason for keeping the promise as affecting the
balance of reasons rather than functioning as a reason to bypass such a
weighing-up process in evaluating what to do. (What they need to justify
breaking the promise, it seems, is first an even stronger reason against bypassing
this process.) Raz thinks that one must appeal to the
value of creating such special relationships to justify the (PO) principle, but
he says that it is beyond the scope of his paper to attempt this justification.
There may well be a defence elsewhere in his writings.
Reference
Raz, J. 1977. Promises and Obligations. In P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality, and Society. Oxford: Clarendon Press.