Definitions from
analytic philosophy
Disclaimer: appearance on this list does not
indicate that a definition is defensible.
Coercion
P coerces Q if and only if:
(1) P aims to keep Q from choosing to
perform action A;
(2) P communicates a claim to Q;
(3) P’s claim indicates that if Q performs
A, then P will bring about some consequence that would make Q’s A-ing less desirable to Q than Q’s not A-ing.
(4) P’s claim is credible to Q.
(5) Q does not do A.
(6) Part of Q’s reason for not doing A is to
lessen the likelihood that P will bring about the consequence announced in (3).
This is a simplified version of Robert Nozick’s 1969
definition taken from The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on coercion.
Action
Explanations
Person X A-ed because he wanted Ø if
and only if:
(1) X wanted
Ø;
(2) X believed (judged, saw) that A-ing was a way for him to achieve Ø under those circumstances;
(3) there was no action believed by X to be
a way for him to bring about Ø, under those circumstances, which X judged
to be as preferable to him as, or more preferable to him than, A-ing;
(4) X had no other want (or set of them)
which, under the circumstances, overrode his want Ø;
(5) X knew how to A.
(6) X was able to A.
Paul Churchland, 1970, “The Logical Character of Action
Explanations,” The Philosophical Review
79, p.221.
Killing
and Letting Die
x killed y if x caused y's death by performing movements
which affect y's body such that y dies as a result of these movement.
x let y die if:
(a) there are conditions affecting y, such
that if they are not altered, y will die.
(b) x has reason to believe that the
performance of certain movements will alter conditions affecting y, such that y
will not die.
(c) x is in a position to perform such
movements.
(d) x fails to perform these movements.
Daniel Dinello, 1971, “On Killing
and Letting Die,” Analysis 31, p.85.
A widow
x is a widow = (a) x is a woman
& (b) x was once
married to some man
& (c) that man died
while married to x
& (d) x has not since
remarried.
Simon Blackburn, 1972, Searle
on Descriptions, Mind LXXXI (323), p.
410.
Descriptive
theory of names
These are the commitments of
the descriptive theory of names, according to Kripke:
1. To every name or designating expression ‘X’, there corresponds a cluster
of properties, namely the family of those properties φ such that A believes ‘φX’.
2. One of the properties, or some conjointly, are
believed by A to pick out some individual uniquely.
3. If most, or a weighted most, of the φ’s are satisfied by one unique object y, then y is
the referent of ‘X’.
4. If the vote does not yield a unique object, then ‘X’
does not refer.
5. The statement ‘If X exists, then X has most of the φ’s’ is known a priori by the speaker.
6. The statement ‘If X exists, then X has most of the φ’s’ is a necessary truth.
C. For any successful theory, the account must not be circular. The
properties which are used in the vote must not themselves use the notion of
reference in a way that is impossible to eliminate.
Saul Kripke,
1972, “Naming and Necessity,” in D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds.), Semantics of natural language,
Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Doxastic incontinence
P’ is held incontinently by S iff:
(i)
S takes P and P’ to be epistemically incompatible;
(ii)
S holds R and R’ and takes these
to be all that is relevant to the epistemic warrant of P and P’ respectively;
(iii)
S takes R epistemically to outweigh R’ and hence P to be more warranted than P’
given R and R’;
(iv)
S holds P’ (and does not hold P).
This definition comes from John
Heil, 1985, Doxastic Incontinence, Mind 93, p. 65.
Bribery
A bribe is a payment of money (or something of value) to another person
in exchange for his giving one special consideration that is incompatible with
the duties of his office, position, or role.
Thomas Carson, 1985, Bribery, Extortion, and “The Foreign Corrupt
Practices Act,” Philosophy & Public
Affairs 14 (1), p. 71.
Literary
Works
A work w is a work of literature if and only if w is produced in a linguistic medium and
1. w is a novel, short story, tale, drama, or poem; and the writer of w
intended that it possess aesthetic, cognitive or interpretation-centered value,
and the work is written with sufficient technical skill for it to be possible
to take that intention seriously; or
2. w possesses aesthetic, cognitive, or interpretation-centered value to
significant degree; or
3. w falls under a predecessor concept to our concept of literature and was
written while the predecessor concept held away; or
4. w belongs to the work of a great writer.
Robert Stecker,
Revue Internationale
de Philosophie 50 (1996).
Joint
Commitment
For any agents a1,…an, a1,…an
are jointly committed to φ when and only when it is common
knowledge amongst a1,…an that
each of a1,…an has expressed
his readiness to enter a joint commitment to with the others among a1,…an.
Thomas H. Smith, 2007, Review of A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds
of Society by Margaret Gilbert, Mind
116, p. 1126.
Suicide
A commits suicide if and
only if A intends that he or she kill
himself or herself (under the description ‘I kill myself’) by an act x, and this intention is fully
satisfied.
Daniel Hill, 2011 “What is it to commit
suicide?” Ratio 24, p. 192.
In tension
“…when I say that these elements of Daly's
view are 'in tension,' I mean that there is sufficient prima facie conflict
such that someone averring both views ought to recognize that they constitute a
surprising conjunction and remark on how, contrary to appearance, they may be
consistent and mutually well-motivated. I suspect this is approximately what
most philosophers mean when they say that various claims are ‘in tension’ with
one another.”
Jonathan Ichikawa, 2011,
Review of Introduction to Philosophical
Methods by Chris Daly. Notre Dame
Philosophical Reviews.
Lying
Definitions have been proposed by various authors. Here are four taken
from a Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy article – there are many more:
(L1) To lie =df to make a believed-false statement
to another person with the intention that the other person believe that
statement to be true.
(L2) To lie =df to make a statement that p, where p is believed
to be false, to another person, with the intention that the other person
believe that p is believed to be true. (Williams 2002, 74,
96–97)
(L3) To lie =df to make a believed-false statement
(to another person), either with the intention that that statement be believed
to be true (by the other person), or with the intention that it be believed (by
the other person) that that statement is believed to be true (by the person
making the statement), or with both intentions. (Mahon 2008, 227–228)
(L4) To lie =df to make a believed-false
statement, to another person or in the believed hearing of another person, with
the intention that some other person—the person addressed or the other person
in the believed hearing—believe some believed-false statement to be true.
(Newey 1997, 100)
James Edwin Mahon, 2016,
“The Definition of Lying and Deception,” In E. Zalta
(ed.), The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition).
Deception
Definitions have been proposed
by various authors. Here are three taken from a Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article – there are more:
(D1) To deceive =df to intentionally cause to have a
false belief that is known or believed to be false.
(D2) A person x deceives
another person y if and only if x intentionally
causes y to believe p, where p is
false and x does not believe that p is true.
(Carson 2010, 48).
(D3) To deceive =df to intentionally cause another
person to have or continue to have a false belief that is known or truly
believed to be false by bringing about evidence on the basis of which the
person has or continues to have the false belief. (Mahon 2007, 189–190)
James Edwin Mahon, 2016,
“The Definition of Lying and Deception,” In E. Zalta
(ed.), The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition).
Empathy
A empathizes with B if and only if three conditions are
met:
(1) A is consciously aware that B is
ψ.
(2) A is consciously aware of what being ψ
feels like.
(3) On the basis of (1) and (2), A
is consciously aware of how B feels.
Joel Smith, 2017, “What is empathy for?” Synthese 194, p.
713.
(The absence of a moral component troubles me!)
Blame
Norm-Specific Criticizability
An agent
is prima facie legitimately criticizable relative to
a specific norm N for Φ-ing iff Φ-ing violates
N.
Norm-Specific Blamelessness
An agent
is blameless relative to a specific norm N for Φ-ing
iff
(1)
Φ-ing is
permissible by N or
(2)
Φ-ing violates
N but the agent Φs
(2.a) in order to comply with the requirements of a (nonoverridden) overriding norm or
(2.b) because this is blamelessly out of her control or
(2.c)
because the agent is blamelessly ignorant that Φ-ing
violates N.
Christoph Kelp and Mona Simion, 2017,
“Criticism and Blame in Action and Assertion,” The Journal of Philosophy 114, p. 79.
Causation and moral
responsibility
If A is morally responsible for
e then e is either an act or omission of A’s or is a causal consequence of an act or omission for which A is morally responsible. (Necessary
condition only.)
Ann Whittle, 2018, “Responsibility in Context,” Erkenntnis 83, p. 166.