The claim that morality is subjective
If someone claims that
morality is subjective, there are a number of things that they might mean. The purpose of this handout is to help
understand this claim, not to evaluate it. I present some positions that a person
who makes the claim might be taking up. I begin with positions that have not
received that much discussion in the philosophical literature, before moving on
to two much discussed positions.
Moral scepticism
If someone says, “People vary in their opinions
about what the moral thing to do is and we have no way of determining whose
opinions are right,” they can be called a moral sceptic. Here is a statement of
moral scepticism:
Moral scepticism: maybe there are moral
truths, but we cannot know whether or not there are such things.
I have called this position moral scepticism because philosophers
use the term ‘scepticism’ to refer to doctrines according to which we cannot
attain a kind of knowledge. External world sceptics think that we cannot know facts
about the external world – we could be dreaming, for example. Other minds
sceptics think we cannot know whether there are other minds – ‘others’ could
just emit sounds and make motions as if they have minds, when they do
not. Sceptics about the mental states of other people think that we cannot know
the mental states of other people – they could be faking.
Warning: I have seen the term ‘moral
scepticism’ used to classify a position which I will present later
on, namely moral error theory. This strikes me as confusing use of
terminology, in light of how the term ‘scepticism’ is commonly
used in philosophy. Scepticism about a given domain does not deny that
there are truths within that domain.
Cultural relativism about
morality
Someone might well say,
“Morality is subjective because it is all culturally relative.” What does
it mean to say that morality is culturally relative, though? I shall offer two
interpretations, but there are probably more.
First interpretation
On the first
interpretation, the claim that morality is culturally relative amounts to an
assertion of two extreme theses, or else a moderation
of the first thesis but without moderating the second thesis:
Simple conditioning thesis: the moral beliefs that a
human being has are the result of them being conditioned in childhood to
believe those things.
Cultural non-universalism: there is diversity
in moral belief and no moral beliefs common to different
cultures.
A worry about the simple
conditioning thesis is that it cannot accommodate the fact that people
sometimes convert from one moral outlook to a significantly different one. A worry about combining both theses together
is that, once you introduce the simple conditioning thesis, it is hard to
understand how there could be so much moral diversity, as the second thesis
asserts, since it is hard to make sense of how novel moral outlooks could
come into being.
Perhaps the simple
conditioning thesis should not be attributed to someone who says that morality
is culturally relative, rather some more moderate thesis. And so there are
variations on an interpretation consisting of the two theses above, which
replace the simple conditioning thesis with something less extreme.
Second interpretation
The two theses
above are consistent with different answers to the question of
whether there are moral truths. Here is a second interpretation of the
claim that morality is culturallly
relative, which treats the moral cultural
relativist as wanting to deny that there are moral truths of
certain kind, often described as absolute moral truths:
Cultural relativity of
moral truth: whether a moral judgement is true or not depends on (i.e., is relative
to) the cultural context in which it is made.
This thesis requires a lot
of further elaboration to properly understand. Here is a proposal to help
understand what it might be getting at. If almost everybody at a certain point
in the past believed that capital punishment is morally right, then during that
time the belief that capital punishment is right is true. Anyone from that time
who denies its truth speaks falsely. If almost everybody at some point in the
future believes that capital punishment is morally wrong, then at this time the
belief that capital punishment is wrong is true. To deny its truth in this time
would be to speak falsely.
This is a toy example –
changes in culture do not tend to be that neat. But even it raises a number of
puzzles, which will cross over to less neat cases. Why not just say
that there is no such thing as moral truth, merely different beliefs about
moral truth? Why instead say that there is somehow a change in what is morally
true as you move from one cultural context to another? Similar issues crop
up if one tries to develop a view of moral truth as relative to the
individual.
Moral error theory
Moral error theory is the
combination of the following two theses:
Moral belief thesis: there are people with moral
beliefs, i.e. beliefs about what is morally right or wrong or good or bad or
required or prohibited, etc.
Moral error thesis: any moral belief and any
statement that expresses an actual or possible moral belief is
false.
A moral error theorist must
reject moral scepticism, as specified above. Contrary to strong moral
scepticism, they think that we can know whether or not there are moral truths:
we can know that there are no moral truths. That puts them at odds with weak
moral scepticism as well. The moral error theorist must also reject the
claim that morality is culturally relative, on the second interpretation. What
is morally true does not change as you move from one culture to another.
Nothing is morally true, for the error theorist, and that remains the case
whatever the moral beliefs are within a culture. One reason for
why some moral subjectivists endorse error theory, over these
positions, is because they accept the authority of science (i.e., the
natural sciences) over the general nature of the world and cannot see how
moral qualities, such as being morally good or bad or required or prohibited, can
fit into the picture of the world’s nature that science offers.
Non-cognitivism
Here is an explanation of
non-cognitivism:
No moral beliefs thesis: there are no moral beliefs;
beliefs are things which can be true or false; what some people think of as
moral beliefs are actually something else, something that cannot be either true
or false.
No moral statements thesis: there are no moral
statements; statements are things which can be true or false; what some people
think of as moral statements are actually something else, something that cannot
be either true or false.
Different kinds of
non-cognitivism offer different accounts of what the something else is in these
theses. Be careful not to assume that they all offer the same
account, e.g. A.J. Ayer’s emotivism. Here is one account. Imagine that
someone you are with sees some food that looks tasty to them in a shop window
and, rather like a cartoon character, licks their lips dramatically. Is what
they do true or false? One plausible response to this question is that what
they do is not the sort of thing that can be true or false, though it can be
sincere or insincere. It can be a sincere or insincere expression of desire.
Someone might think that what appear to be moral statements are like this. To
say, ‘Capital punishment is wrong,’ is not to make a statement, rather to
express a desire for the world to be a certain way, much as the person in the
example expresses a desire to taste the food. Correspondingly, there is no
moral belief that capital punishment is wrong, just a desire.
Non-cognitivism rejects a
commitment common to most other forms of moral subjectivism: that there
are moral beliefs. To accept this commitment is to be a cognitivist.